The people, groups and businesses behind the control of BTC stole the Bitcoin name and to this day pretend that BTC is Bitcoin. They do this to fool the market and the general masses into buying into their pyramid scheme and false narrative.
When something pretends to be something else, its promoters intentionally reinforce this false belief, often because they are making money out of the lie.
https://www.claims.co.uk/knowledge-base/intellectual-property/passing-off
Your willingness to step up to contribute your words & evidence to this case. You will need to download and complete the forms provided below and be able to provide the relevant evidence.
Miners, businesses, small holders.
No.
Dr Craig Wright is meeting all costs. After the case is successful, Dr Wright will be reimbursed for all his expenses. The remainder will be appropriately divided among the community, businesses, and others affected.
The Deed of Promise is the document where Dr Wright binds himself to any excess from the proceedings to be reinvested into the Bitcoin community to build and restore the Bitcoin ecosystem.
Yes, by submitting your witness statement.
Dr Wright is representing himself in his capacity as a legal expert and lawyer, yet each witness statement is support for all of us.
To be included as an Intervener in this application, individuals or entities (miners, developers, businesses) must provide evidence demonstrating that they have suffered financial or operational harm as a result of BTC Core’s changes to the Bitcoin protocol.
Specifically, they must show that their investments, projects, or business models were based on the immutability of the original Bitcoin protocol and that these were undermined by BTC Core’s unilateral modifications.
Impact on Small Holders: Transaction Costs Exceeding ValueThe following will give you an example of some types of things you can say. Note while I’m giving examples of this needs to be your own words and you need to be able to demonstrate each of the areas factually. ~ Dr Craig S Wright
When I invested in Bitcoin, part of the appeal was its promise as a system for low-value, everyday transactions. Like many small holders, I believed that Bitcoin could be used as a form of digital cash—enabling me to store and transact small amounts without incurring significant costs. At the time of my investment, Bitcoin was promoted as a scalable and low-fee network, making it ideal for small transactions, such as sending small payments or making micro-purchases.
However, due to changes in the protocol introduced by BTC Core, this is no longer the case. The transaction fees on the Bitcoin (BTC) network have increased dramatically, often exceeding the value of the small amounts I hold. As a result, the cost of moving or spending my Bitcoin has become prohibitively expensive, effectively locking me out of using or transferring my funds.
For example, if I hold a small amount of Bitcoin worth $50, attempting to make a transaction could incur fees of $10 or more, meaning that I would lose a significant percentage—or even all—of the value in fees alone. This reality contradicts the original promise of Bitcoin, where small transactions were meant to be affordable and accessible to everyone, regardless of the amount they held.
For small holders like myself, BTC Core’s changes have rendered Bitcoin unusable for its original purpose as digital cash. Instead of being able to transact freely and move small amounts without excessive cost, I am now unable to use or transfer my Bitcoin without suffering financial loss. This has caused me and other small holders to lose money, as the cost of transacting often exceeds the value of the Bitcoin we own.
BTC Core’s changes have therefore not only devalued my investment but have also made it impossible for small holders to participate in the Bitcoin network as originally intended. This shift towards high transaction costs undermines Bitcoin’s utility and has made it a system that only benefits large holders, while small holders are effectively left behind.
1. Draft the Application:
2. Statement of Case:
3. Attach Supporting Evidence (detailed in Step 2 below):
1. Proof of Investment in Mining Hardware:
2. Evidence of Operational Impact:
3. Expert Reports (Optional):
1. Personal Witness Statement:
2. Supporting Testimony (Optional):
1. Direct and Substantial Interest:
2. Need for Full Adjudication:
3. Detrimental Reliance and Harm:
1. Preempt Counterarguments:
2. Prepare for Hearings:
By following these steps, miners can successfully apply to intervene in the proceedings, demonstrating their detrimental reliance on BTC Core’s assurances and the financial harm caused by the protocol changes. The process involves gathering solid evidence, submitting witness statements, and making a strong legal argument under CPR Rule 19.2 and relevant case law. Miners' participation will be essential to providing the court with a comprehensive view of the harm caused by BTC Core’s actions and ensuring a just resolution.
1. Draft the Application:
2. Statement of Case:
3. Attach Supporting Evidence (detailed in Step 2 below):
1. Proof of Reliance on the Original Protocol:
2. Evidence of Abandoned or Rewritten Projects:
3. Financial Evidence of Loss:
1. Personal Witness Statement:
2. Supporting Testimony from Team Members:
1. Direct and Substantial Interest:
2. Need for Full Adjudication:
3. Detrimental Reliance and Financial Harm:
1. Preempt Counterarguments:
2. Prepare for Oral Testimony:
1. Establish Detrimental Reliance:
2. Direct and Substantial Interest:
3. Proof of Financial Harm:
4. Prove Unilateral Control by BTC Core:
1. Transparency Requirements for BTC Core:
2. Restoring Decentralisation:
3. Equal Access to Information:
Developers who wish to intervene in the case must submit a strong, evidence-backed application that demonstrates detrimental reliance on BTC Core’s assurances and the significant financial harm caused by unilateral protocol changes. By following the legal framework of CPR Rule 19.2, presenting clear documentary evidence, and addressing relevant legal precedents, developers can make a compelling case for joining the proceedings as Interveners. Their participation is crucial to providing the court with a complete understanding of how BTC Core’s actions impacted software development efforts and stifled innovation within the broader Bitcoin ecosystem. Through transparent witness statements, expert reports, and detailed financial evidence, developers can ensure that their voices are heard and that their contributions to the ecosystem are fully recognised in the court’s adjudication of the case.
1. Draft the Application:
2. Statement of Case:
3. Attach Supporting Evidence (detailed in Step 2 below):
1. Proof of Reliance on the Original Protocol:
2. Evidence of Operational Disruption:
3. Financial Losses and Reduced Revenues:
4. Expert Reports (Optional):
1. Business Owner or Executive Statement:
2. Supporting Statements from Key Employees:
1. Direct and Substantial Interest:
2. Necessity for Full Adjudication:
3. Detrimental Reliance and Harm:
1. Preempt Counterarguments:
2. Prepare for Oral Testimony:
1. Establish Detrimental Reliance:
2. Direct and Substantial Interest:
3. Prove Financial Harm and Operational Impact:
1. Restoring Fair Competition:
2. Preventing Future Centralisation:
3. Financial Compensation:
1. Draft the Application:
2. Statement of Case:
3. Attach Supporting Evidence (detailed in Step 2 below):
1. Proof of Reliance on the Original Protocol:
2. Evidence of Financial Harm:
3. Impact on Investment Strategy or Savings:
1. Personal Witness Statement:
2. Expert Testimonies (Optional):
1. Direct and Substantial Interest:
2. Need for Full Adjudication:
3. Detrimental Reliance and Harm:
1. Preempt Counterarguments:
2. Prepare for Oral Testimony:
1. Establish Detrimental Reliance:
2. Direct and Substantial Interest:
In the case of winemakers in the Champagne region, individual winemakers typically do not own the goodwill associated with the term "Champagne." Instead, they hold a right linked to the use of a protected geographical indication (PGI), which allows them to use the name "Champagne" as part of the collective regional designation. The ownership of the goodwill associated with the term "Champagne" is held collectively by the region as a whole, protected under French and European Union law.
The right to use "Champagne" is based on the appellation d'origine contrôlée (AOC) system, which regulates the designation under strict guidelines. Thus, individual producers have a right to use the name "Champagne" under this system but do not individually own the goodwill; the goodwill is legally attributed to the broader regional designation, ensuring that only wines produced within the Champagne region and meeting the AOC standards can use the name. This protection prevents others outside the region from exploiting the goodwill of "Champagne."
The ownership of the name "Champagne" lies not with individual winemakers but within the broader, collective framework established through the appellation d'origine contrôlée (AOC) and Protected Geographical Indication (PGI) systems, which are enforced under both French and EU law. These systems ensure that "Champagne" as a designation is safeguarded and may only be used by producers within the defined geographical boundaries of the Champagne region, provided they adhere to stringent production standards and quality controls.
Under this framework, individual winemakers are granted the right to use the "Champagne" name as part of a collective identity rather than as individual property. The Court of Justice of the European Union (CJEU) case law, including cases like Comité Interprofessionnel du Vin de Champagne (CIVC) v Aldi Süd Dienstleistungs-GmbH & Co. OHG (C-393/16), demonstrates that "Champagne" is protected as a geographical indication. In the Aldi case, the CJEU reinforced that names associated with such geographical indications must remain exclusive to products genuinely originating from the defined area and produced under prescribed standards. This prevents non-Champagne producers from benefitting from the reputation associated with the Champagne name, thereby safeguarding its distinctiveness.
Thus, individual winemakers contribute to and share in the collective recognition and value associated with "Champagne." However, the goodwill linked to "Champagne" does not reside with any single winemaker but is, in essence, pooled and protected within the legal boundaries of the region as a whole. The control and protection of the name are managed by bodies such as the Comité Interprofessionnel du Vin de Champagne (CIVC), which act to preserve the integrity of the Champagne designation, ensuring that it remains exclusive to wines genuinely meeting the criteria established by the AOC.
In English law, rights associated with the goodwill in champagne trading cases—or any case involving trademarks, branding, and reputation linked to a product—are held by the party that has established the recognition and reputation tied to specific goods or services. Goodwill is generally viewed as an asset that attracts customers and can be intrinsic to a brand, meriting legal protection. In champagne-related cases, case law focuses on geographic origin and brand identity, which are essential in establishing rights and protection over goodwill.
One leading case on goodwill is Irvine v Talksport Ltd [2002] EWHC 367 (Ch), where Eddie Irvine, a well-known Formula One driver, succeeded in an action for passing off when his image was used without permission, leveraging the goodwill associated with his reputation. The court highlighted that goodwill represents a proprietary right, acting as an “attractive force” that brings in custom, established through continuous and deliberate use in commerce. In champagne trading, a similar principle applies; goodwill in the brand and reputation of a champagne producer, such as Moët & Chandon, is linked to the business responsible for cultivating customer loyalty and brand recognition.
Furthermore, AG Spalding & Bros v AW Gamage Ltd [1915] 84 LJ Ch 449 provides a foundation for understanding rights linked to goodwill in England. This case sets out the three essential elements required to succeed in a passing-off action, which involves protecting goodwill: the plaintiff must show they possess goodwill, that there has been misrepresentation by the defendant, and that damage has resulted from this misrepresentation. In champagne trading, if a competitor used a well-known brand’s name or image to market their champagne, the aggrieved brand could potentially claim a right over the goodwill and seek redress, provided these conditions are met.
Another instructive case is Erven Warnink BV v J Townend & Sons (Hull) Ltd [1979] AC 731, known as the “Advocaat” case. This case reinforced the notion that goodwill is tied to the distinctiveness and reputation of a product originating from a specific source. The House of Lords ruled that using the name “Advocaat” for a non-authentic product constituted passing off, affirming that goodwill is intrinsically tied to both the product’s origin and its branding characteristics. Champagne is particularly susceptible to such considerations, given its protected designation of origin under EU law. This implies that the goodwill associated with any “champagne” product should rightly align with producers in the Champagne region, France, who maintain its recognised standards and reputation. Thus, even in UK courts, rights linked to goodwill in champagne trading would typically favour producers who meet this regional criterion.
In conclusion, English case law suggests that in champagne trading, the rights linked to goodwill are generally vested in the entity that has established a recognised and respected reputation connected to the specific champagne product or brand. This protection is further supported by trademark rights and the protected designation of origin status, resonating with cases like Spalding and Advocaat, which underscore the critical role of brand distinctiveness and geographic origin in establishing and maintaining rights over goodwill.
The principles surrounding goodwill and rights in English law, particularly those seen in champagne trading cases, can be analogously applied to Bitcoin, especially in regard to the distinctiveness of the term “Bitcoin” and its original protocol. Just as Champagne producers rely on a protected designation to establish rights based on a collective reputation and region, Bitcoin’s foundational design—asserted to be “set in stone” by its creator, Satoshi Nakamoto—creates a distinctive protocol that builds and sustains its own unique form of goodwill. Those who adhere to the original protocol can thus claim rights tied to this distinctiveness, akin to the appellation controls in Champagne, where only authentic products from the defined region meet the criteria.
In Irvine v Talksport Ltd [2002], where the court held that the goodwill associated with Eddie Irvine’s image and reputation entitled him to protection, a similar argument could be made for those following Bitcoin’s original protocol. Just as Irvine’s use of his identity was legally safeguarded against unauthorised exploitation, rights associated with the term "Bitcoin" can be argued for under the assurance that the protocol’s design would remain fixed, thereby providing recognisable, original characteristics that differentiate it from versions altered by developments like SegWit and Taproot.
The AG Spalding & Bros v AW Gamage Ltd [1915] case, where goodwill protection required proof of a unique reputation, misrepresentation, and subsequent damage, underpins a similar framework for Bitcoin. Adherents to the original protocol might argue that changes to Bitcoin (BTC) misrepresent the original system, creating a situation where those who followed the initial “set in stone” assurance face harm through deviation. This could allow those original adherents to claim rights based on the distinctiveness of Bitcoin’s original design, where any alternative use of the name “Bitcoin” that strays from these core principles could be construed as misleading.
Erven Warnink BV v J Townend & Sons (Hull) Ltd [1979], or the “Advocaat” case, further strengthens this concept of rights based on origin and product integrity. Just as the term "Advocaat" was protected to ensure authenticity, the distinct term “Bitcoin” can be similarly argued to carry rights for those adhering to the original protocol, safeguarding the term from alterations that obscure its foundational design. This case’s emphasis on the specific origin of products supports the argument that the rights to the term “Bitcoin” are held by those who uphold the protocol as originally intended, safeguarding it from misrepresentative changes in function or appearance.
In the context of promissory estoppel, those who committed resources based on Satoshi’s assurance that Bitcoin’s protocol was “set in stone” may claim a right to maintain that original protocol’s integrity. Alterations that deviate from the original promises could be viewed as undermining this commitment, just as non-authentic products misrepresent Champagne. Consequently, the term “Bitcoin” itself, like “Champagne” or “Advocaat,” might carry rights not of ownership per se but of authenticity, linking the term directly to the original protocol and those who uphold it.
In English law, the rights associated with Bitcoin's original protocol, much like those seen in champagne trading cases, are rooted in maintaining authenticity rather than ownership of the name "Bitcoin." The rights do not lie in the name itself but in adherence to the original protocol's distinctive, immutable characteristics. Promissory estoppel could support those following the original design, as any deviation undermines the reliance on Satoshi’s assurance that the protocol was “set in stone.” This reliance creates a claim to uphold the protocol’s consistency, akin to the collective rights in geographic indications like "Champagne," which protect authenticity and prevent misrepresentation without individual ownership of the designation.
Under a promissory estoppel argument, Dr. Wright might not claim ownership of the name "Bitcoin" per se, but if there were an assurance that the protocol and its foundational elements were “set in stone” and he then built upon it in reliance on that assurance, he could argue he holds a right linked to the use of the name or system, akin to a vested interest.
Promissory estoppel in this scenario would focus on any promise or representation that Bitcoin's protocol or branding would remain unchanged. If it can be established that a promise was made (explicitly or implicitly) to maintain a stable foundation for Bitcoin's structure, and Dr. Wright acted in reliance on this assurance by dedicating resources or development efforts, he might then have an enforceable right or interest—though not outright ownership—based on that reliance. This right would be connected to the expectation created by the initial representation, and his reliance could, theoretically, give him standing to prevent actions that undermine or alter what was “set in stone.”
Such a right would not equate to direct ownership of goodwill or trademark but would instead be a form of reliance-based protection, giving Dr. Wright a claim to uphold the protocol's consistency if deviations infringe upon his investment or commitment made under the promise of immutability.
In the context of Bitcoin, applying the concept of promissory estoppel would focus on Satoshi Nakamoto’s assurances that the protocol was "set in stone." This promise of immutability, if relied upon by individuals like Dr. Wright who have invested in Bitcoin's original design and functionality, could indeed create enforceable rights, even if those rights do not translate into outright ownership of the Bitcoin name or protocol itself. Promissory estoppel would recognise a vested interest in maintaining the integrity of the protocol, particularly where individuals have relied on these assurances to their detriment by dedicating resources, development, or capital under the belief that the foundational elements of Bitcoin would remain unaltered.
Under English case law, the doctrine of promissory estoppel allows a party to prevent another from reneging on a promise when the promisee has relied on that promise to their detriment. The case of Central London Property Trust Ltd v High Trees House Ltd [1947] KB 130 established that if a party makes a clear representation intending another to act upon it, and the latter relies on it, that representation may be binding. Applying this to Bitcoin, Dr. Wright could argue that the foundational promise that Bitcoin's protocol was "set in stone" represented an assurance upon which he and others relied. If significant investments or contributions were made in reliance on this stability, they could assert that a departure from the original protocol breaches that foundational promise, invoking promissory estoppel to prevent deviation from the original design.
If Dr. Wright—and others following the original protocol—have acted on the assumption that Bitcoin’s design would remain fixed, their reliance is akin to the regional producers in the Champagne analogy. In this case, their actions would not confer outright ownership of Bitcoin’s name or protocol but would create a legitimate claim tied to the expectation of stability. This would mean that any modifications, like SegWit or Taproot, which alter Bitcoin’s core mechanics, might be seen as infringing upon the rights established through reliance on the protocol's immutability.
This vested right, though not a direct ownership of goodwill or trademark, would serve as a reliance-based protection, allowing Dr. Wright to argue for the protocol's consistency and integrity under the original principles. This argument aligns with cases like Combe v Combe [1951] 2 KB 215, which clarified that promissory estoppel does not grant new rights in itself but prevents the promisor from acting in a way that contradicts the original promise if reliance is shown. Dr. Wright could thus claim a right to uphold the original protocol if changes to it undermine the commitment he made, supported by the understanding that Bitcoin was “set in stone.”
By invoking promissory estoppel, Dr. Wright could also establish that individuals who follow the original protocol are similarly protected by this reliance. Such a position would not equate to ownership of Bitcoin’s name but rather confer a standing to maintain the protocol's adherence to its original promises, preventing others from redefining Bitcoin and, consequently, misrepresenting the original system. This aligns with English common law, which supports the idea that reliance on a clear representation of intention, such as Bitcoin’s protocol immutability, creates enforceable rights to prevent deviation if detriment and reliance can be demonstrated.
In sum, Dr. Wright’s claim would hinge on the argument that, like the Champagne designation, the original Bitcoin protocol represents a collective, region-like identity defined by immutability. Under promissory estoppel, anyone adhering to this original protocol could assert rights based on this shared reliance, fostering continuity and protecting the "goodwill" of the original design against modifications that could otherwise infringe on the expectations initially established by Satoshi Nakamoto’s representation.
To provide a fully extended and rigorous analysis, distinguishing Dr. Wright’s position under promissory estoppel from the concept of collective ownership as seen in Champagne cases, it is essential to explore the nature of ownership, rights, and goodwill in a detailed, multi-layered manner. This analysis will examine the legal and philosophical foundations of ownership in English law, how collective rights function in geographically protected products like Champagne, and the role of promissory estoppel as a reliance-based right rather than a proprietary claim. By doing so, we can delineate the scope of Dr. Wright’s interest in Bitcoin as distinct from any proprietary or ownership-based claim, clarifying why his reliance under promissory estoppel does not confer rights in the Bitcoin name or system but rather secures his adherence to an immutable protocol.
Ownership in English law is one of the most comprehensive rights a person or entity can have over property, including both tangible and intangible assets. Ownership encompasses a range of rights—commonly referred to as a "bundle of rights"—that include the right to possess, use, modify, transfer, and exclude others. English law traditionally views ownership as providing extensive control over an asset, granting the owner the ability to utilise it to the fullest extent, unless legally restricted.
The Champagne case represents a unique model in which ownership of the name “Champagne” is not held by individual winemakers but is vested collectively in the Champagne region. This model, enforced under French and EU law, illustrates a geographically defined form of collective ownership, wherein individual producers have a right to use the name provided they adhere to specific production standards. This structure differs fundamentally from traditional ownership as it operates under collective rights linked to geographical designation and regulatory control, rather than individual, transferrable ownership.
Dr. Wright’s reliance on the promise that Bitcoin’s protocol was “set in stone” does not confer ownership or proprietary rights in the name “Bitcoin.” Rather, his position is grounded in promissory estoppel, which provides a reliance-based right without the ability to control, alter, or exclusively claim the asset. Promissory estoppel operates under equity to prevent a promisor from deviating from an assurance upon which the promisee has relied to their detriment.
The collective ownership in Champagne, which grants enforceable rights over the designation, fundamentally differs from the reliance-based protection of promissory estoppel. Champagne’s model illustrates that a group can exercise control over a name without individual proprietary rights, while promissory estoppel allows only for reliance without control or enforceability.
English case law on ownership and promissory estoppel underscores that Dr. Wright’s position does not equate to ownership of Bitcoin. His reliance-based right aligns with the integrity of the original protocol, not with control, alteration, or the ability to prevent third-party usage. This reliance lacks the enforceability and exclusivity found in both Champagne’s collective ownership and traditional proprietary rights in goodwill.
Dr. Wright’s reliance on promissory estoppel grants him the right to follow the original Bitcoin protocol, akin to a user-right without control or ownership. This right, while personal and enforceable against the promisor, does not confer the collective enforcement, exclusivity, or proprietary interest seen in Champagne’s collective ownership model. Consequently, Dr. Wright’s position under promissory estoppel does not contravene the court’s restriction on claiming goodwill or proprietary rights in Bitcoin. His interest is limited to adherence to the original protocol, a conditional right that contrasts with both traditional ownership and the collective ownership seen in Champagne’s designation.
To thoroughly examine the concept of database rights under UK law, particularly focusing on individuals who have not created the database but have significantly invested in it, an analysis is needed of the legal framework that protects database creators, owners, and significant investors. Database rights in the UK, under the Copyright and Rights in Databases Regulations 1997 (SI 1997/3032), provide protection to databases where substantial investment in obtaining, verifying, or presenting content has been made. This protection creates an exclusive right for the database maker, but there exists a nuanced distinction between the rights of the database owner and those of other contributors or investors.
Under UK law, database rights are an intellectual property (IP) protection designed specifically for databases, separate from copyright. These rights are sui generis, meaning they are distinct from other IP protections, aiming to secure the structure and content organisation of a database when there has been a substantial investment in its development.
The rights of individuals who have not created the database but have invested significantly in its development are less straightforward. UK law does not automatically confer ownership of database rights to investors or contributors who did not make the database but have invested resources into it. However, these individuals may still obtain certain reciprocal or conditional rights depending on the nature of their investment and agreements made with the database owner.
III. Distinguishing Ownership from Reciprocal Rights in Database Law
To effectively differentiate between ownership rights and reciprocal rights for significant investors in databases, it is crucial to understand how UK law structures exclusive control and access in relation to the original investment.
Ownership of a database right requires that the holder has made a substantial investment in creating or structuring the database. This requirement is a key distinction between rights held by creators or owners and those held by later investors.
Distinguishing ownership from other rights in databases has significant legal implications, particularly in terms of enforcement, access, and commercial value.
Conclusion: Ownership Versus Reciprocal Rights in UK Database Law
In UK law, database rights firmly belong to the creator or maker who directed the initial investment into structuring the database, providing them with exclusive control over extraction and reuse. Significant investors who contribute post-creation, although essential in sustaining or expanding the database, do not gain ownership rights. Their rights are defined reciprocally, often secured by contract, allowing conditional access but falling short of the control or enforcement powers intrinsic to ownership. This delineation protects the integrity of the database owner’s investment while permitting flexibility for contributors, who can use but not claim rights to the database structure itself.
To argue that, under UK law, those who wish to use a database protected by database rights need the permission of the right-holder and that Satoshi Nakamoto, as the original maker, holds these rights, we must explore how database rights operate and how promissory estoppel enables Dr. Wright to enforce the original protocol. This analysis will demonstrate that database rights are exclusive to the maker, granting control over access and reuse, and that Dr. Wright’s enforcement ability arises not from ownership but from reliance on Nakamoto’s promise, secured under promissory estoppel.
Database rights in the UK, introduced through the Copyright and Rights in Databases Regulations 1997, grant protection to databases where a substantial investment has been made in obtaining, verifying, or presenting data. These rights are distinct from copyright, focusing on the structure and content of the database itself rather than any underlying data.
To apply these principles to the Bitcoin protocol, we assume that Satoshi Nakamoto, as the creator of the Bitcoin database, holds the original database rights. By virtue of substantial investment in developing, verifying, and arranging the protocol’s structure, Nakamoto would qualify as the database maker, with exclusive control over extraction and reuse rights.
While Nakamoto holds the database rights, Dr. Wright’s position does not stem from ownership but rather from reliance on Nakamoto’s assurance that the protocol would remain “set in stone.” This reliance is protected by promissory estoppel, enabling Dr. Wright to enforce Nakamoto’s promise and preserve the integrity of the original protocol against unauthorised changes.
Dr. Wright’s enforcement rights under promissory estoppel differ fundamentally from ownership, creating a distinct form of reciprocal right that allows enforcement of Nakamoto’s promise without the power to alter or transfer the protocol.
Given Nakamoto’s status as the original right-holder, any third party wishing to use the Bitcoin database must obtain permission to ensure their actions do not infringe upon database rights. Dr. Wright’s role under promissory estoppel reinforces this requirement, as he has the authority to prevent unauthorised alterations, preserving the protocol’s intended form.
Under UK law, database rights rest exclusively with the maker—in this case, Satoshi Nakamoto—who retains control over extraction, reuse, and any changes to the protocol. Dr. Wright, however, possesses a distinct, reciprocal right under promissory estoppel to enforce Nakamoto’s original terms. His role is to uphold Nakamoto’s promise, ensuring that third parties obtain permission or adhere strictly to the unaltered protocol. This reliance-based enforcement right allows Dr. Wright to act as a protector of the original database framework without claiming ownership or control, illustrating how promissory estoppel can create reciprocal rights that enforce database integrity in the absence of direct ownership.
In UK law, the distinction between ownership in rights and the ability to enforce revolves around the breadth and depth of control, exclusivity, and transferability associated with each concept. Ownership in rights encompasses a comprehensive set of entitlements that allow the owner not only to control the use and exploitation of the asset but also to transfer, modify, or even exclude others entirely. Enforceability, on the other hand, refers to the narrower ability to uphold specific terms or conditions related to the asset, typically grounded in legal or equitable doctrines such as promissory estoppel. Enforceability permits action to maintain compliance with agreed terms but lacks the full spectrum of powers inherent to ownership.
Ownership is the most extensive form of legal entitlement, providing the owner with broad control over the asset and a range of powers that extend beyond mere usage.
Enforceability refers to a narrower legal ability, typically based on equitable doctrines or contractual agreements, allowing a party to compel adherence to specific terms without possessing ownership. This ability is rooted in reliance or reciprocal arrangements rather than the broader control inherent in ownership.
Ownership provides the most extensive authority over an asset, encompassing exclusive, transferrable, and alienable rights. In contrast, enforceability through mechanisms like promissory estoppel is a protective right, preventing specific breaches of agreed terms without extending ownership’s full range of powers.
In summary, ownership is comprehensive and multifaceted, granting exclusive and alienable rights over an asset, whereas enforceability through promissory estoppel is a specific, reliance-based right focused solely on maintaining compliance with original terms. This distinction positions ownership as a far wider concept, encompassing both control and discretion over an asset, while enforceability is protective, restricted to preserving agreed conditions without extending ownership’s full breadth of powers.
In examining the nature of database rights for early miners of the Bitcoin protocol, it is essential to distinguish between the rights they acquire through their participation in the database’s creation and the concept of ownership held by Satoshi Nakamoto as the original creator. Early miners possess certain rights as a result of their involvement in building the database, but these rights are markedly different from ownership in several critical ways. Specifically, the rights of early miners are non-transferable, limited in scope, and do not confer the full spectrum of control that ownership entails. This analysis will delve into the implications of these distinctions, referencing English case law to clarify the breadth and exclusivity inherent in ownership versus the restricted, non-transferable nature of the rights of early miners.
Under UK law, database rights are granted to those who make a substantial investment in obtaining, verifying, or presenting data, as codified in the Copyright and Rights in Databases Regulations 1997. Early miners, by virtue of their participation in the formation of the Bitcoin database, contribute to its development and thus acquire certain rights associated with their role in creating the data structure.
Ownership in English law confers the widest possible set of entitlements over an asset, including exclusive control, the ability to exclude others, and the right to transfer or modify the asset at will. English case law on ownership underscores that it involves not only usage rights but also full autonomy over the asset, which includes the ability to alienate or dispose of it entirely.
The rights of early miners differ from ownership in scope, as they lack the broad autonomy and transferability associated with true ownership. Their rights are limited to usage within the original framework set by the database’s creator and do not include the power to control or modify the protocol.
As the original creator of the Bitcoin protocol, Nakamoto holds ownership of the database rights, including full control, exclusivity, and transferability, setting a sharp contrast to the conditional rights of early miners. This ownership allows Nakamoto to determine the protocol’s usage, while early miners are restricted to following the original terms without the authority to transfer or alter their rights.
The distinction between ownership and the rights held by early miners underscores how UK law reserves database ownership for those with full investment-based entitlements, while granting limited, enforceable rights to those who participated without creating the database. This approach maintains the integrity of ownership, restricting it to those with primary investment and creation roles, while enabling others to use the database in compliance with the original terms.
In summary, UK law draws a clear line between ownership, with its wide scope, transferability, and exclusivity, and the non-transferable, limited rights held by early miners. Nakamoto’s ownership of the database rights includes the ability to exclude, transfer, and control usage, a full proprietary entitlement. In contrast, early miners have conditional, non-transferable rights tied to their participation but lack any authority to modify or alienate the database. Dr. Wright’s position, grounded in promissory estoppel, allows enforcement of Nakamoto’s original terms without conferring the comprehensive powers of ownership, marking a distinct difference between reliance-based rights and the broad, autonomous nature of ownership.